publick economic
publick The exercise
No loss offsets
So far it has been assumed that
losses may be set fully against tax; this may not however be the case. To see
whether the results depend crucially on the assumption. We now consider the
extreme case of no loss offsets: where the return to the risky asset equais if and x otherwise. Initially, we can contrast
the tax and no-tax situations. Later we compare taxes with different degrees of
loss offset.
To see the effect of
the tax (without loss offset), let us take the special two-state case with the
return in the second state negative. A dollar invested in the risky asset now
yields an extra in state (1) and in state (2), so that the downward slope of
the budget line is
This is steeper; i.e.,
the absence of teh loss offset provision makes the risky asset less attractive
at the margin, relative to the no-tax situation. It does not however follow
that this kind of income tax will necessarily discourage risk-taking, since
there is in addition the wealth effect. This is illustrated by Fig. 4-6 for the
case where r=0. The no-tax budget line is ST, the with-tax line is ST’. The
move from p to p’ may be decomposed into a wealth effect PQ and the movement
round the indifference curve QP’. The net result may be seen from the fact that
the vertikal distance from S to P’ in Fig. 4-6 is equal to ; in other words, it is an index of the amount
invested in the risky asset. Depending of the wealth elasticity of demand, this
may decrease or increase, the latter being shown in Fig. 4-6. Even therefore
without loss offsets it is possible that social risk-taking may be increased by
income taxation.
On
the other hand, with sufficiently large tax rates, the demand for risky asset
is reduced where there are no loss offsets. To see this, all we have to observe
is taht for tax rates near 100 per cent, almost the entire portfolio is
allocated to the safe asset. This follows because, as the tax rate approaches
100 per cent, the maximum return on the risky asset approaches zero and the
expected return becomes negative. Since the indifference curves are convex, the
demand curves for the different assets are continuous functions of the tax
rate.
We turn now to the
comparison of taxes with and without loos affsets. It seems likely taht a
reduction in the extent to which losses can be set against tax will reduce
risk-taking. The effect does however depend on the basis for comparison. To
examine this, let us assume that α of losses can be
offset . Then, if the tax rate
is held constant, so that expected revenue falls (and expected utility rises)
as α
is increased, we can show that denote the affter-tax return to the risky
asset with loss offsets provosion, α, and r^ the after-tax
return to the safe asset, so taht terminal wealth
is,................................................................................
Now on the right-hand side c^x^/ is strictly positive where x < 0 and zero
otherwise. It follows that the second term is evaluated only at positive values
(where then x^<r^ and U”<0), and that the whole
right-hand side is positive. Since the coefficient of is positive, it follows that α
is increased.
This
conclusion does not however necessarily hold where the tax without loss offsets
has a lower tax rate. Suppose, for example, that we compare taxes with equal
expected utility. Since the removal of the loss offset provosion unambiguously
makes individuals worse off in all states in which losses are incrurred, it is
clear that to compensate the tax rate must be lower. Thus, for any particular
portfolio allocation, the pattern of returns is such that there is a larger
probability of very small and very large incomes. The new distribution. To
analyse the consequences for portfolio allocation, we use general result of
Diamond and Stiglitz (1974). To do this, we note that, since U is by assumption
a strictly increasing function of A, and hence of x, we may therefore invert
this relationship and write the first-order condition (4-17)
as,......................................
The
basic result which can now be used is that an increase in the dispersion of a
random variable, keeping the mean constant, increase the expected value of a
convex function and decreases that of a concave function. Applying this to
left-hand side of the first order condition (4-18), the removal of loss offsets
leads to an increase in the dispersion of U, and hence to a fall in the
expected value where the function is concave. It is left
as an exercise to the reader to explore the relationship between this condition
and the properties of absolute and relative risk aversion (and whether they are
increasing or decreasing). It can be shown that it is by no means guaranteed
that social risk-taking is lower as a result of the (expected
utility-preserving) reduction in the loss offset provision (see Diamond and
Stiglitz, 1974).
The
empirical relevance of the no-loss offset case depends of the form of a
country’s income tax law, and on the range of an individual’s economic
activities. Where losses may be set against other forms of income, where losses
may be carried forward, and where capital losses may be set against investment
income, the full loss offset case may be a reasonable approximation. On the
other hand, there are typica;;y restrictions on the transfer of losses (e.g.,
capital losses not being eligible for relief on income tax) or where no
carry-over is allowed. The no-loss offset case may therefore be more
applicable.
A
natural question to ask is why tax authorities so commonly impose limitations
on the extent to which losses are to be
offset. After all, it is exactly in those situations where individuals incur
losses that risk-sharing with the goverment ought to be important. The answer
is that it is extremely difficult for the goverment to distinguish, in many
cases, between production and comsuption activities. An individual coul raise
horses because he enjoys raising horses, or he could raise horse as a
meaningful economic activity, i.e., for profit. The goverment would not like to subsidize the
former, but might not want to discriminate against the lateer as an econimic
activity. They only way it can distinguish is to require the individual who
claims that he is raising the horses for profit to make a profit. If he return
out to be unsuccessful, then he is classified as having embarked on the
activity for enjoyment, even if that were not his motive (and even if he hates
horses).
Limited
deductibility of interest
If
interest expenses are not deductible, there is a kink in the budget constraint
at the point where all of the individual’s wealth is invested in the risky
asset, i.e., below and to the right of the point T in Fig. 4-1. The effect
depends on the balance of the substitution effect, which discourages
risk-taking by individuals who
previously borrowed, and the wealth effect.
Exercise
4-4 examine the effect of not allowing interest deductibility (but with full
loss offsets) and how it depends on the properties of the wealth-portfolio
locus.
Again,
we can enquire into the reason for this limitation which some (but not all)
countries impose ; again, we find the answer in limitations on the government’s
ability to identify the objective of borrowing. For example, a parent could, in
principle, give a dollar to his child, and have the child lend the dollar back
to parent ; the parent then could pay an arbitrary amount of interest to the
child. This is a mechanism by which income from the parent could be transferred
to the child ; so long as the two have different marginal rates, it is
desirable for them to do this. In fact, of course, restrictions are imposed on
the rates of interest that could “quality” ; but there is clearly room for
considerable discretion in transferring income from one taxpayer to another.
Similarly,
the ability to deduct interest enable individuals to take advantage of special
provisions of the tax code. For instance, in the united states interest on
municipal bonds is tax-exempt. Consider an individual with a 70 per cent marginal
tax rate. Assume the borrowing rate is 10 per cent, but the interest rate on
municipal bonds is at 7 per cent. He borrows $100. He pays @10 in interest
every year, which is tax-deductible, so his “net cost” is $3. He receives $7 in
tax-free interest. Thus, for a zero investment, he receives annually $4.
Obviously, if he could do this he would demand bonds up to the point where his
marginal tax rate falls to 30 per cent. In fact, there are restrictions in that
one cannot borrow to buy tax-free bonds, but since funds are fungible, he may
be able to borrow to current consumption, and use what he would have spent on
current consumption to purchase bonds.
Exemption of capital gains
Most
countries provide special treatment of capital gains. Levying lower rate of tax
than on other forms of investment income. In this section we examine the
extreme case where there is no tax on capital gains : the extension to the case
of partial exemption should be apparent to the reader. The implication depend
on the characterization of the two assets. For purpose of illustration we
assume that the safe asset yields a return solely in the form of taxable
interest, and that the return to the risky asset is entirely capital gains
(again the extension to the partial case is immediate). Although this is a
caricature, it allows us to examine the frequently made assertion that the
special provisions for capital gains
encourage investment in risky assets.
Terminal
wealth now becomes, with a tax at rate on the safe asset only
Again,
the slope of the budget constraint is altered by the tax, but in contrast to
the no-loss offset case it now slopes less steeply. Moreover, it continues to
pass through T (since at this point individual is neither holding the safe
asset not borrowing)-see Fig. 4-7. Suppose now that we consider the
indifference curve passing through the new equilibrium P’. Q is the point on
this curve with the same slope as the original budget line, and it is clear
that we can again distinguish a “wealth” effect
(P to Q) and subtitution effect (Q to P’). The latter is in the
direction of increased risk-taking. The former depends on the wealth elasticity
of demand for the risky asset, but where this is greater than it operates to
reduce risk-taking. This is illustrated by Fig. 4-7. From (4-19) we can see
that tax, for a given value of a, reduces the wealth in each state nature by
the same absolute amount. The locus of points of constant values of a has
therefore a slope of 45--see the dashed kine
through P in Fig. 4-7. If the wealth elasticity of demand for the risky asset
is positive, then the slope of the wealth-portfolio locus is less than 45 (refer back to Fig. 4-2), and Q involves a
lower value of α, and hance lower social risk-taking,
than at P. As shown, the net effect is for risk-taking to increase (P’ is below
the dashed line). However, it is quite possible for the tax on the safe asset
to reduce risk-taking, counter-intuitive though that may seen. As in other
situations. The substituation effect operating in the expected direction may be
more than offset by the wealth effect.
The
justification sometimes given for the exemtion of capital gains, or for their
being taxed at a lower rate, is that this provision encourages risk-taking. In
this section we have seen that this is not necessarily the case : the outcome
depends on the properties of the asset demand function.
Komentar
Posting Komentar